Steven Pinker: Language and Thinking
"言語は、人間の本性を反映した、人間の集団的創造物である。現実をどのように概念化するか、そしてどのように互いに関係するか。そして、言語のさまざまな癖や複雑さを分析することで、私たちは、言語がどのようなものであるかを知ることができると思います。私たちを動かしているものを知る窓を得ることができると思うのです。" "Language is a collective human creation, reflecting human nature, how we conceptualize reality, and how we relate to one another. And then, by analyzing the various quirks and complexities of Language, I think we can get a window onto what makes us tick."
Steven Pinker: Language and Thinking
In a special preview of his book, "Thinking Languages," Steven Pinker explains the language and how it expresses the human mind -- and how the words we choose communicate our intentions.
// A //
1)
That is a picture of Maurice Druon, the Honorary Perpetual Secretary of L'Academie Francaise, the French Academy.
He is splendidly attired in his 68,000-dollar uniform, befitting the role of the French Academy as legislating the correct usage of French and perpetuating the language.
The French Academy has two main tasks:
it compiles a dictionary of official French.
They're now working on their ninth edition, which they began in 1930, and they've reached the letter P.
They also legislate on correct usages, such as the proper term for what the French call "email," which ought to be "courriel."
The French are told that the World Wide Web ought to be referred to as "la toile d'araignee mondiale" - the Global Spider Web - recommendations that the French gaily ignore.
2)
Now, this is one model of how language comes to be:
namely, it's legislated by an academy.
But anyone who looks at language realizes that this is a rather silly conceit, that language, instead, emerges from human minds interacting with one another.
And this is visible in the unstoppable change in language - the fact that by the time the Academy finishes its dictionary, it will already be well out of date.
We see it in the constant appearance of slang and jargon, the historical change in languages, the divergence of dialects, and the formation of new languages.
3)
So language is not a creator or shaper of human nature, so much as a window onto human nature.
In a book that I'm currently working on, I hope to use language to shed light on human nature, including the cognitive machinery with which humans conceptualize the world and the relationship types that govern human interaction.
And I'm going to say a few words about each one this morning.
4)
Let me start with a technical problem in language that I've been worried about for quite some time and indulge in my passion for verbs and how they're used.
The problem is, which verbs go in which constructions?
The verb is the chassis of the sentence.
It's the framework onto which the other parts are bolted.
5)
Let me give you a quick reminder of something that you've long forgotten.
An intransitive verb, such as "dine," can't take a direct object.
You have to say, "Sam dined," not, "Sam dined the pizza."
A transitive verb mandates that there has to be an object there:
"Sam devoured the pizza."
You can't just say, "Sam devoured."
There are dozens or scores of verbs of this type, each of which shapes its sentence.
6)
So, a problem in explaining how children learn the language,
a problem in teaching language to adults so that they don't make grammatical errors,
and pain in programming computers to use language in which verbs go in constructions.
7)
For example, the dative construction in English.
You can say, " Give a muffin to a mouse," the prepositional dative.
Or, " Give a mouse a muffin," the Double-object dative.
"Promise anything to her," "Promise her anything," and so on.
Hundreds of verbs can go both ways.
8)
So a tempting generalization for a child, for an adult, for a computer is that any verb that can appear in the construction,
"Subject-thing-to-a-recipient" can also be expressed as "subject-verb-recipient-thing."
A handy thing to have because language is infinite,
and you could not say parrot back the sentences that you've heard.
You've got to extract generalizations to produce and understand new sentences.
This would be an example of how to do that.
9)
Unfortunately, there appear to be specific exceptions.
You can say, "Biff drove the car to Chicago,"
but not, "Biff drove Chicago the car."
You can say, "Sal gave Jason a headache,"
but it's a bit odd to say, "Sal gave a headache to Jason."
10)
The solution is that these constructions, despite their initial appearance, are not synonymous,
that when you crank up the microscope on human cognition,
you see that there's a subtle difference in meaning between them.
// B //
11)
So, "give the X to the Y," that construction corresponds to the thought "cause X to go to Y." Whereas "give the Y the X" corresponds to the idea "cause Y to have X."
Now, many events can be subject to either construal, kind of like the classic figure-ground reversal illusions, in which you can either pay attention to the particular object,
in which case the space around it recedes from awareness,
or you can see the faces in the area, in which case the thing reduces out of consciousness.
12)
How are these construals reflected in language?
In both cases, the thing that is construed as being affected is expressed as the direct object, the noun after the verb.
So, when you think of the event as causing the muffin to go somewhere where you're doing something to the muffin , you say, "Give the muffin to the mouse."
When you construe it as "cause the mouse to have something,"
you're doing something to the mouse,
and therefore, you express it as, "Give the mouse the muffin."
13)
So which verbs go in which construction the problem with which began depends on whether the verb specifies a kind of motion or a kind of possession change.
To give something involves both causing something to go and causing someone to have.
To drive the car only causes something to go because Chicago's not the kind of thing that can possess something.
Only humans can possess things.
And to give someone a headache causes them to have the headache, but it's not as if you're taking the headache out of your head and causing it to go to the other person and implanting it in them.
You may be loud or obnoxious, or another way is causing them to have a headache.
14)
So, that's an example of the kind of thing that I do in my day job.
So why should anyone care?
Well, there are a number o exciting conclusions, I think, from this and many similar kinds of analyses of hundreds of English verbs.
15)
First, there's a level of fine-grained conceptual structure,
We automatically and unconsciously compute every time we produce or utter a sentence, which governs our use of language.
You can think of this as the language of thought, or "mentalese."
It seems to be based on a fixed set of concepts,
which governs dozens of constructions and thousands of verbs in English and in all other languages fundamental concepts such as space, time causation, and human intention, such as what is the means and what is the ends?
These are reminiscent of the kinds of categories that Immanuel Kant argued are the basic framework for human thought,
and interestingly, our unconscious use of language seems to reflect these Kantian categories.
It doesn't care about perceptual qualities, such as color, texture, weight, and speed, which virtually never differentiate the use of verbs in different constructions.
16)
An additional twist is that all of the constructions in English are used not only literally but in a quasi-metaphorical way.
For example, this construction, the dative, is used not only to transfer things but also for the symbolic transfer of ideas, as when we say, "She told a story to me" or "told me a story,"
"Max taught Spanish to the students" or "taught the students Spanish."
It's precisely the same construction, but no muffins, no mice, nothing moving.
It evokes the container metaphor or communication, in which we conceive ideas as objects, sentences as containers, and communication as a sending.
As when we say we "gather" our ideas, to "put" them "into" words, and if they aren't "empty" or "hollow," we might get these ideas "across" to a listener,
who can "unpack" our words to "extract" their "content."
17)
And indeed, this kind of vocabulary is not the exception but the rule.
It's tough to find any example of abstract language that is not based on some concrete metaphor.
18)
For example, you can use the verb "go" and the prepositions "to" and "from" in a literal, spatial sense.
"The messenger went from Paris to Istanbul."
You can also say, "Biff went from sick to well."
He needn't go anywhere. He could have been in bed the whole time, but it's as if his health is a point in state space that you conceptualize as moving.
Or, "The meeting went from three to four," in which we conceive of time as stretched along a line.
Likewise, we use "force" to indicate not only physical force, as in, "Rose forced the door to open," but also interpersonal force,
as in, "Rose forced Sadie to go," not necessarily by maltreating her, but by issuing a threat.
Or, "Rose forced herself to go," as if there were two entities inside Rose's head engaged in a tug of war.
// C //
19)
The second conclusion is that the ability to conceive of a given event in two different ways,
such as "cause something to go to someone" and "causing someone to have something,"
I think it is a fundamental feature of human thought, and it's the basis for much human argumentation, in which people don't differ so much on the facts as on how they ought to be construed.
To give you a few examples:
For example, "ending a pregnancy" versus "killing a fetus."
"a ball of cells" versus "an unborn child;."
"invading Iraq" versus "liberating Iraq;"
"redistributing wealth" versus "confiscating earnings."
And I think the giant picture of all would take seriously the fact that so much of our vocabulary about abstract events is based on a concrete metaphor
and see human intelligence itself as consisting of a repertoire of concepts
such as objects, space, time, causation, and intention, which are helpful in a social, knowledge-intensive species, whose evolution you can well imagine,
and a process of symbolic abstraction that allows us to bleach these concepts of their original conceptual content space, time, and force
and apply them to new abstract domains, therefore allowing a species that evolved to deal with rocks and tools and animals,
to conceptualize mathematics, physics, law, and other conceptual domains.
20)
Well, I said I'd talk about two windows on human nature the cognitive machinery with which we conceptualize the world,
and now I'm going to say a few words about the relationship types that govern human social interaction, again, as reflected in language.
And I'll start with a puzzle, the puzzle of indirect speech acts.
21)
I'm sure most of you have seen the movie "Fargo."
And you might remember the scene in which the kidnapper is pulled over by a police officer, is asked to show his driver's license, and holds his wallet out with a 50-dollar bill extending at a slight angle out the wallet.
And he says, "I was just thinking that maybe we could take care of it here in Fargo,"
which everyone, including the audience, interprets as a veiled bribe.
22)
This kind of indirect speech is rampant in language.
For example, in polite requests, if someone says, "If you could pass the guacamole, that would be awesome,"
we know what he means, even though that's a rather bizarre concept.
"Would you like to come up and see my etchings?" I think most people understand the intent behind that.
And likewise, if someone says, "Nice store you've got there. It would be a real shame if something happened to it," we understand that as a veiled threat rather than an amusing of hypothetical possibilities.
So the puzzle is, why are bribes, polite requests, solicitations, and threats so often veiled?
No one's fooled.
Both parties know what the speaker means, and the speaker knows the listener knows that the speaker knows that the listener knows, etc., etc.,
So what's going on?
23)
I think the key idea is that language is a way of negotiating relationships, and human relationships fall into several types.
There's an influential taxonomy by the anthropologist Alan Fiske, in which relationships can be categorized, more or less, into commonality, which works on the principle
"what's mine is thine, what's thine in mine,"
the kind of mindset that operates within a family, for example;
dominance, whose principle is "don't mess with me;."
reciprocity, "you scratch my back, I'll scratch yours;."
and sexuality, in the immortal words of Cole Porter, "Let's do it."
24)
Now, relationship types can be negotiated.
Even though there are default situations in which one of these mindsets can be applied, they can be stretched and extended.
For example, communality applies most naturally within family or friends,
but it can be used to transfer the mentality of sharing to groups that ordinarily would not be disposed to exercise it.
For example, in brotherhoods, fraternal organizations, sororities, locutions like "the family of man,"
you try to get people who are not related to use the relationship type that would ordinarily be appropriate to close kin.
25)
Now, mismatches can be awkward when one person assumes one relationship type and another takes a different one.
If you went over and helped yourself to a shrimp off your boss' plate, that would be an awkward situation.
Or if a dinner guest after the meal, that would be somewhat awkward.
In less blatant cases, there's still a negotiation that often goes on.
For example, there's often tension over whether an employee can socialize with the boss or refer to them on a first-name basis in the workplace.
If two friends have a reciprocal transaction, like selling a car,
it's well known that this can be a source of tension or awkwardness.
// D //
26)
In dating, the transition from friendship to sex can lead to, notoriously, various forms of awkwardness, and as can sex in the workplace,
We call the conflict between a dominant and a sexual relationship "sexual harassment."
Well, what does this have to do with language?
As a social interaction, language has to satisfy two conditions.
You have to convey the actual content here; we get back to the container metaphor.
You want to express the bribe, the command, the promise, the solicitation, and so on,
but you also have to negotiate and maintain the kind of relationship you have with the other person.
27)
The solution, I think, is that we use language at two levels:
the literal form signals the safest relationship with the listener,
whereas the implicated content, the reading between the lines that we count on the listener to perform, allows the listener to derive the interpretation which is most relevant in context,
which possibly initiates a changed relationship.
The simplest example of this is in the polite request.
If you express your request as a conditional "If you could open the window, that would be great."
even though the content is imperative, the fact that you're not using the critical voice means that you're not acting as if you're in a relationship of dominance,
where you could presuppose the other person's compliance.
28)
On the other hand, you want the damn guacamole.
By expressing it as an if-then statement, you can get the message across without appearing to boss another person around.
And more subtly, I think this works for all of the veiled speech acts involving plausible deniability:
the bribes, threats, propositions, solicitations, and so on.
29)
One way of thinking about it is to imagine what it would be like if language - where could only be used literally.
And you can think of it in terms of a game-theoretic payoff matrix.
Put yourself in the position of the kidnapper wanting to bribe the officer.
There's a high stake in the two possibilities of having a dishonest officer or an honest officer.
If you don't bribe the officer, you will get a traffic ticket or, as is the case of "Fargo," worse, whether the honest officer is honest or dishonest.
Nothing ventured, nothing gained.
In that case, the consequences are rather severe.
30)
On the other hand, if you extend the bridge, you get a massive payoff of going free if the officer is dishonest.
If the officer is honest, you get a massive penalty for being arrested for bribery.
So this is a somewhat fraught situation.
31)
On the other hand, with indirect language, if you issue a veiled bribe,
then the dishonest officer could interpret it as a bribe, in which case you get the payoff of going free.
The honest officer can't hold you to it as a bridge, and therefore, you get the nuisance of the traffic ticket.
So you get the best of both worlds.
And a similar analysis, I think, can apply to the potential awkwardness of a sexual solicitation,
and other cases where plausible deniability is an asset.
I think this affirms something that's long been known by diplomats
namely, that the vagueness of language, far from being a bug or an imperfection,
actually might be a feature of the language that we use to our advantage in social interactions.
32)
SO, to sum up:
language is a collective human creation, reflecting human nature,
how we conceptualize reality, and how we relate to one another.
And then, by analyzing the various quirks and complexities of language,
I think we can get a window onto what makes us tick.
Thank you very much.
Steven Pinker: Language and Thinking
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=LjQM8PzCEY0